CHAPTER XIV. OF PREROGATIVE.
Sect. 159.
WHERE
the
legislative
and
executive
power
are
in
distinct
hands, (as
they
are
in
all
moderated monarchies,
and
well-framed governments)
there
the
good
of
the
society
requires,
that
several
things
should
be
left
to
the
discretion
of
him
that
has
the
executive
power:
for
the
legislators
not
being
able
to
foresee,
and
provide
by
laws,
for
all
that
may
be
useful
to
the
community,
the
executor
of
the
laws
having
the
power
in
his
hands, has
by
the
common
law
of
nature
a
right
to
make
use
of
it
for
the
good
of
the
society,
in
many
cases,
where
the
municipal
law
has
given
no
direction,
till
the
legislative
can
conveniently
be
assembled
to
provide
for
it.
Many
things
there
are,
which
the
law
can
by
no
means
provide
for;
and
those
must
necessarily
be
left
to
the
discretion
of
him
that
has
the
executive
power
in
his
hands,
to
be
ordered
by
him
as
the
public
good
and
advantage
shall
require: nay,
it
is
fit
that
the
laws
themselves
should
in
some
cases
give
way
to
the
executive
power,
or
rather
to
this
fundamental
law
of
nature
and
government, viz.
That
as
much
as
may
be,
all
the
members
of
the
society
are
to
be
preserved:
for
since
many
accidents
may
happen,
wherein
a
strict
and
rigid
observation
of
the
laws
may
do
harm; (as
not
to
pull
down
an
innocent
man's
house
to
stop
the
fire,
when
the
next
to
it
is
burning)
and
a
man
may
come
sometimes
within
the
reach
of
the
law,
which
makes
no
distinction
of
persons,
by
an
action
that
may
deserve
reward
and
pardon; 'tis fit
the
ruler
should
have
a power,
in
many
cases,
to
mitigate
the
severity
of
the
law,
and
pardon
some
offenders:
for
the
end
of
government
being
the
preservation
of
all,
as
much
as
may
be,
even
the
guilty
are
to
be
spared,
where
it
can
prove
no
prejudice
to
the
innocent. Sect. 160.
This
power
to
act
according
to
discretion,
for
the
public good,
without
the
prescription
of
the
law,
and
sometimes
even
against it,
is
that
which
is
called
prerogative:
for
since
in
some
governments
the
lawmaking power
is
not
always
in
being,
and
is
usually
too
numerous,
and
so
too
slow,
for
the
dispatch
requisite
to
execution;
and
because
also
it
is
impossible
to
foresee,
and
so
by
laws
to
provide
for,
all
accidents
and
necessities
that
may
concern
the
public,
or
to
make
such
laws
as
will
do
no
harm,
if
they
are
executed
with
an
inflexible
rigour,
on
all
occasions,
and
upon
all
persons
that
may
come
in
their
way;
therefore
there
is
a
latitude
left
to
the
executive
power,
to
do
many
things
of
choice
which
the
laws
do
not
prescribe. Sect. 161.
This
power, whilst
employed
for
the
benefit
of
the
community,
and
suitably
to
the
trust
and
ends
of
the
government,
is
undoubted prerogative,
and
never
is
questioned:
for
the
people
are
very
seldom
or
never
scrupulous
or
nice
in
the
point;
they
are
far
from
examining
prerogative, whilst
it
is
in
any
tolerable
degree
employed
for
the
use
it
was
meant,
that
is,
for
the
good
of
the
people,
and
not
manifestly against it:
but
if
there
comes
to
be
a
question
between
the
executive
power
and
the
people,
about
a
thing
claimed
as
a prerogative;
the
tendency
of
the
exercise
of
such
prerogative
to
the
good
or
hurt
of
the
people,
will
easily
decide
that
question. Sect. 162.
It
is
easy
to
conceive,
that
in
the
infancy
of
governments,
when
commonwealths
differed
little
from
families
in
number
of
people,
they
differed
from
them
too
but
little
in
number
of
laws:
and
the
governors, being
as
the
fathers
of
them,
watching
over
them
for
their
good,
the
government
was
almost
all
prerogative. A
few
established
laws
served
the
turn,
and
the
discretion
and
care
of
the
ruler supplied
the
rest.
But
when
mistake
or
flattery
prevailed
with
weak
princes
to
make
use
of
this
power
for
private
ends
of
their
own,
and
not
for
the
public good,
the
people
were
fain
by
express
laws
to
get
prerogative
determined
in
those
points
wherein
they
found disadvantage
from
it:
and
thus
declared
limitations
of
prerogative
were
by
the
people
found
necessary
in
cases
which
they
and
their
ancestors
had left,
in
the
utmost
latitude,
to
the
wisdom
of
those
princes
who
made
no
other
but
a
right
use
of
it,
that
is,
for
the
good
of
their
people. Sect. 163.
And
therefore
they
have
a
very
wrong
notion
of
government,
who
say,
that
the
people
have
encroached
upon
the
prerogative,
when
they
have
got
any
part
of
it
to
be
defined
by
positive laws:
for
in
so
doing
they
have
not
pulled
from
the
prince
any
thing
that
of
right
belonged
to
him,
but
only
declared,
that
that
power
which
they
indefinitely left
in
his
or
his
ancestors
hands,
to
be
exercised
for
their
good,
was
not
a
thing
which
they
intended
him
when
he
used
it
otherwise:
for
the
end
of
government
being
the
good
of
the
community, whatsoever
alterations
are
made
in
it,
tending
to
that
end, cannot
be
an
encroachment
upon
any
body,
since
no
body
in
government
can
have
a
right
tending
to
any
other
end:
and
those
only
are
encroachments
which
prejudice
or
hinder
the
public good.
Those
who
say
otherwise,
speak
as
if
the
prince had a
distinct
and
separate
interest
from
the
good
of
the
community,
and
was
not
made
for
it;
the
root
and
source
from
which
spring
almost
all
those
evils
and
disorders
which
happen
in
kingly
governments.
And
indeed,
if
that
be
so,
the
people
under
his
government
are
not
a
society
of
rational
creatures,
entered
into
a
community
for
their
mutual good;
they
are
not
such
as
have
set
rulers
over
themselves,
to
guard,
and
promote
that
good;
but
are
to
be
looked
on
as
an
herd
of
inferior
creatures
under
the
dominion
of
a master,
who
keeps
them
and
works
them
for
his
own
pleasure
or
profit.
If
men
were
so
void
of
reason,
and
brutish,
as
to
enter
into
society
upon
such
terms,
prerogative
might
indeed
be,
what
some
men
would
have
it,
an
arbitrary
power
to
do
things
hurtful
to
the
people. Sect. 164.
But
since
a
rational
creature
cannot
be
supposed,
when
free,
to
put
himself
into
subjection
to
another,
for
his
own
harm; (though,
where
he
finds a
good
and
wise
ruler,
he
may
not
perhaps
think
it
either
necessary
or
useful
to
set
precise
bounds
to
his
power
in
all
things)
prerogative
can
be
nothing
but
the
people's permitting
their
rulers
to
do
several
things,
of
their
own
free
choice,
where
the
law
was
silent,
and
sometimes
too
against
the
direct
letter
of
the
law,
for
the
public good;
and
their
acquiescing
in
it
when
so
done:
for
as
a
good
prince,
who
is
mindful
of
the
trust
put
into
his
hands,
and
careful
of
the
good
of
his
people, cannot
have
too
much
prerogative,
that
is, power
to
do
good;
so
a
weak
and
ill
prince,
who
would
claim
that
power
which
his
predecessors
exercised
without
the
direction
of
the
law,
as
a
prerogative
belonging
to
him
by
right
of
his
office,
which
he
may
exercise
at
his
pleasure,
to
make
or
promote
an
interest
distinct
from
that
of
the
public,
gives
the
people
an
occasion
to
claim
their
right,
and
limit
that
power, which, whilst
it
was
exercised
for
their
good,
they
were
content
should
be
tacitly
allowed. Sect. 165.
And
therefore
he
that
will
look
into
the
history
of
England,
will
find,
that
prerogative
was
always
largest
in
the
hands
of
our
wisest
and
best
princes;
because
the
people,
observing
the
whole
tendency
of
their
actions
to
be
the
public good,
contested
not
what
was
done
without
law
to
that
end: or,
if
any
human
frailty
or
mistake (for princes
are
but
men,
made
as
others)
appeared
in
some
small
declinations
from
that
end;
yet
'twas visible,
the
main
of
their
conduct
tended
to
nothing
but
the
care
of
the
public.
The
people
therefore,
finding
reason
to
be
satisfied
with
these
princes, whenever
they
acted
without,
or
contrary
to
the
letter
of
the
law,
acquiesced
in
what
they
did, and,
without
the
least
complaint,
let
them
inlarge
their
prerogative
as
they
pleased,
judging
rightly,
that
they
did
nothing
herein
to
the
prejudice
of
their
laws,
since
they
acted
conformable
to
the
foundation
and
end
of
all
laws,
the
public good. Sect. 166.
Such
god-like princes
indeed
had
some
title
to
arbitrary
power
by
that
argument,
that
would
prove
absolute
monarchy
the
best
government,
as
that
which
God
himself
governs
the
universe
by;
because
such
kings
partake
of
his
wisdom
and
goodness.
Upon
this
is
founded
that
saying,
That
the
reigns
of
good
princes
have
been
always
most
dangerous
to
the
liberties
of
their
people:
for
when
their
successors,
managing
the
government
with
different
thoughts,
would
draw
the
actions
of
those
good
rulers
into
precedent,
and
make
them
the
standard
of
their
prerogative,
as
if
what
had been
done
only
for
the
good
of
the
people
was
a
right
in
them
to
do,
for
the
harm
of
the
people,
if
they
so
pleased;
it
has
often
occasioned
contest,
and
sometimes public disorders,
before
the
people
could
recover
their
original
right,
and
get
that
to
be
declared
not
to
be
prerogative,
which
truly
was
never
so;
since
it
is
impossible
that
any
body
in
the
society
should
ever
have
a
right
to
do
the
people
harm;
though
it
be
very
possible,
and
reasonable,
that
the
people
should
not
go
about
to
set
any
bounds
to
the
prerogative
of
those
kings,
or
rulers,
who
themselves
transgressed
not
the
bounds
of
the
public good:
for
prerogative
is
nothing
but
the
power
of
doing public
good
without
a rule. Sect. 167.
The
power
of
calling
parliaments
in
England,
as
to
precise
time, place,
and
duration,
is
certainly a
prerogative
of
the
king,
but
still
with
this
trust,
that
it
shall
be
made
use
of
for
the
good
of
the
nation,
as
the
exigencies
of
the
times,
and
variety
of
occasions,
shall
require:
for
it
being
impossible
to
foresee
which
should
always
be
the
fittest
place
for
them
to
assemble
in,
and
what
the
best
season;
the
choice
of
these
was
left
with
the
executive
power,
as
might
be
most
subservient
to
the
public good,
and
best
suit
the
ends
of
parliaments. Sect. 168.
The
old
question
will
be
asked
in
this
matter
of
prerogative,
But
who
shall
be
judge
when
this
power
is
made
a
right
use
of
one
answer:
between
an
executive
power
in
being,
with
such
a prerogative,
and
a legislative
that
depends
upon
his
will
for
their
convening,
there
can
be
no
judge
on
earth;
as
there
can
be
none
between
the
legislative
and
the
people,
should
either
the
executive,
or
the
legislative,
when
they
have
got
the
power
in
their
hands, design,
or
go
about
to
enslave
or
destroy
them.
The
people
have
no
other
remedy
in
this,
as
in
all
other
cases
where
they
have
no
judge
on
earth,
but
to
appeal
to
heaven:
for
the
rulers,
in
such
attempts,
exercising
a power
the
people
never
put
into
their
hands, (who
can
never
be
supposed
to
consent
that
any
body
should
rule
over
them
for
their
harm)
do
that
which
they
have
not
a
right
to
do.
And
where
the
body
of
the
people,
or
any
single man,
is
deprived
of
their
right,
or
is
under
the
exercise
of
a power
without
right,
and
have
no
appeal
on
earth,
then
they
have
a
liberty
to
appeal
to
heaven, whenever
they
judge
the
cause
of
sufficient
moment.
And
therefore,
though
the
people
cannot
be
judge,
so
as
to
have,
by
the
constitution
of
that
society,
any
superior
power,
to
determine
and
give
effective
sentence
in
the
case;
yet
they
have,
by
a
law
antecedent
and
paramount
to
all
positive
laws
of
men, reserved
that
ultimate
determination
to
themselves
which
belongs
to
all
mankind,
where
there
lies
no
appeal
on
earth, viz.
to
judge,
whether
they
have
just
cause
to
make
their
appeal
to
heaven.
And
this
judgment
they
cannot
part
with,
it
being
out
of
a man's power
so
to
submit
himself
to
another,
as
to
give
him
a
liberty
to
destroy
him;
God
and
nature
never
allowing
a
man
so
to
abandon
himself,
as
to
neglect
his
own
preservation:
and
since
he
cannot
take
away
his
own
life,
neither
can
he
give
another
power
to
take
it.
Nor
let
any
one
think,
this
lays
a
perpetual
foundation
for
disorder;
for
this
operates
not,
till
the
inconveniency
is
so
great,
that
the
majority
feel it,
and
are
weary
of
it,
and
find a
necessity
to
have
it
amended.
But
this
the
executive
power,
or
wise
princes,
never
need
come
in
the
danger
of:
and
it
is
the
thing,
of
all
others,
they
have
most
need
to
avoid,
as
of
all
others
the
most
perilous.