CHAPTER XVI. OF CONQUEST.
Sect. 175.
THOUGH
governments
can
originally
have
no
other
rise
than
that
before
mentioned,
nor
polities
be
founded
on
any
thing
but
the
consent
of
the
people;
yet
such
have
been
the
disorders
ambition
has
filled
the
world
with,
that
in
the
noise
of
war,
which
makes
so
great
a
part
of
the
history
of
mankind,
this
consent
is
little
taken notice of:
and
therefore
many
have
mistaken
the
force
of
arms
for
the
consent
of
the
people,
and
reckon
conquest
as
one
of
the
originals
of
government.
But
conquest
is
as
far
from
setting
up
any
government,
as
demolishing
an
house
is
from
building a
new
one
in
the
place. Indeed,
it
often
makes
way
for
a
new
frame
of
a commonwealth,
by
destroying
the
former; but,
without
the
consent
of
the
people,
can
never
erect
a
new
one. Sect. 176.
That
the
aggressor,
who
puts
himself
into
the
state
of
war
with
another,
and
unjustly
invades
another
man's right, can,
by
such
an
unjust war,
never
come
to
have
a
right
over
the
conquered,
will
be
easily
agreed
by
all
men,
who
will
not
think,
that
robbers
and
pyrates
have
a
right
of
empire
over
whomsoever
they
have
force
enough
to
master;
or
that
men
are
bound
by
promises,
which
unlawful
force
extorts
from
them.
Should
a
robber
break
into
my house,
and
with
a
dagger
at
my
throat
make
me
seal
deeds
to
convey
my
estate
to
him,
would
this
give
him
any
title?
Just
such
a title,
by
his
sword, has
an
unjust conqueror,
who
forces
me
into
submission.
The
injury
and
the
crime
is
equal,
whether
committed
by
the
wearer
of
a crown,
or
some
petty
villain.
The
title
of
the
offender,
and
the
number
of
his
followers,
make
no
difference
in
the
offence, unless
it
be
to
aggravate
it.
The
only
difference
is,
great
robbers
punish
little
ones,
to
keep
them
in
their
obedience;
but
the
great
ones
are
rewarded
with
laurels
and
triumphs,
because
they
are
too
big
for
the
weak
hands
of
justice
in
this
world,
and
have
the
power
in
their
own
possession,
which
should
punish
offenders.
What
is
my
remedy
against a robber,
that
so
broke
into
my house?
Appeal
to
the
law
for
justice.
But
perhaps
justice
is
denied,
or
I
am
crippled
and
cannot stir,
robbed
and
have
not
the
means
to
do
it.
If
God
has taken
away
all
means
of
seeking
remedy,
there
is
nothing
left
but
patience.
But
my son,
when
able,
may
seek
the
relief
of
the
law,
which
I
am
denied:
he
or
his
son
may
renew
his
appeal,
till
he
recover
his
right.
But
the
conquered,
or
their
children,
have
no
court,
no
arbitrator
on
earth
to
appeal
to.
Then
they
may
appeal,
as
lephtha did,
to
heaven,
and
repeat
their
appeal
till
they
have
recovered
the
native
right
of
their
ancestors,
which
was,
to
have
such
a legislative
over
them,
as
the
majority
should
approve,
and
freely
acquiesce
in.
If
it
be
objected,
This
would
cause
endless
trouble; I answer,
no
more
than
justice
does,
where
she
lies
open
to
all
that
appeal
to
her.
He
that
troubles
his
neighbour
without
a cause,
is
punished
for
it
by
the
justice
of
the
court
he
appeals
to:
and
he
that
appeals
to
heaven
must
be
sure
he
has
right
on
his
side;
and
a
right
too
that
is
worth
the
trouble
and
cost
of
the
appeal,
as
he
will
answer
at
a
tribunal
that
cannot
be
deceived,
and
will
be
sure
to
retribute
to
every
one
according
to
the
mischiefs
he
hath
created
to
his
fellow
subjects;
that
is,
any
part
of
mankind:
from
whence
it
is
plain,
that
he
that
conquers
in
an
unjust
war
can
thereby
have
no
title
to
the
subjection
and
obedience
of
the
conquered. Sect. 177.
But
supposing
victory
favours
the
right
side,
let
us
consider
a
conqueror
in
a
lawful
war,
and
see
what
power
he
gets,
and
over
whom. First,
It
is
plain
he
gets
no
power
by
his
conquest
over
those
that
conquered
with
him.
They
that
fought
on
his
side
cannot
suffer
by
the
conquest,
but
must
at
least
be
as
much
freemen
as
they
were
before.
And
most
commonly
they
serve
upon
terms,
and
on
condition
to
share
with
their
leader,
and
enjoy
a
part
of
the
spoil,
and
other
advantages
that
attend
the
conquering
sword;
or
at
least
have
a
part
of
the
subdued
country
bestowed
upon
them.
And
the
conquering
people
are
not, I hope,
to
be
slaves
by
conquest,
and
wear
their
laurels
only
to
shew
they
are
sacrifices
to
their
leaders
triumph.
They
that
found
absolute
monarchy
upon
the
title
of
the
sword,
make
their
heroes,
who
are
the
founders
of
such
monarchies, arrant Draw-can-sirs,
and
forget
they
had
any
officers
and
soldiers
that
fought
on
their
side
in
the
battles
they
won,
or
assisted
them
in
the
subduing,
or
shared
in
possessing,
the
countries
they
mastered.
We
are
told
by
some,
that
the
English
monarchy
is
founded
in
the
Norman
conquest,
and
that
our
princes
have
thereby
a title
to
absolute
dominion:
which
if
it
were
true, (as
by
the
history
it
appears
otherwise)
and
that
William
had a
right
to
make
war
on
this
island;
yet
his
dominion
by
conquest
could
reach
no
farther
than
to
the
Saxons
and
Britons,
that
were
then
inhabitants
of
this
country.
The
Normans
that
came
with
him,
and
helped
to
conquer,
and
all
descended
from
them,
are
freemen,
and
no
subjects
by
conquest;
let
that
give
what
dominion
it
will.
And
if
I,
or
any
body
else,
shall
claim
freedom,
as
derived
from
them,
it
will
be
very
hard
to
prove
the
contrary:
and
it
is
plain,
the
law,
that
has
made
no
distinction
between
the
one
and
the
other,
intends
not
there
should
be
any
difference
in
their
freedom
or
privileges. Sect. 178.
But
supposing,
which
seldom
happens,
that
the
conquerors
and
conquered
never
incorporate
into
one
people,
under
the
same
laws
and
freedom;
let
us
see
next
what
power a
lawful
conqueror
has
over
the
subdued:
and
that
I
say
is
purely despotical.
He
has
an
absolute
power
over
the
lives
of
those
who
by
an
unjust
war
have
forfeited
them;
but
not
over
the
lives
or
fortunes
of
those
who
engaged
not
in
the
war,
nor
over
the
possessions
even
of
those
who
were
actually engaged
in
it. Sect. 179. Secondly, I
say
then
the
conqueror
gets
no
power
but
only
over
those
who
have
actually assisted, concurred,
or
consented
to
that
unjust
force
that
is
used against him:
for
the
people
having
given
to
their
governors
no
power
to
do
an
unjust thing,
such
as
is
to
make
an
unjust war, (for
they
never
had
such
a power
in
themselves)
they
ought
not
to
be
charged
as
guilty
of
the
violence
and
unjustice
that
is
committed
in
an
unjust war,
any
farther
than
they
actually
abet
it;
no
more
than
they
are
to
be
thought
guilty
of
any
violence
or
oppression
their
governors
should
use
upon
the
people
themselves,
or
any
part
of
their
fellow
subjects,
they
having
empowered
them
no
more
to
the
one
than
to
the
other. Conquerors,
it
is
true,
seldom
trouble
themselves
to
make
the
distinction,
but
they
willingly
permit
the
confusion
of
war
to
sweep
all
together:
but
yet
this
alters
not
the
right;
for
the
conquerors
power
over
the
lives
of
the
conquered, being
only
because
they
have
used
force
to
do,
or
maintain
an
injustice,
he
can
have
that
power
only
over
those
who
have
concurred
in
that
force;
all
the
rest
are
innocent;
and
he
has
no
more
title
over
the
people
of
that
country,
who
have
done
him
no
injury,
and
so
have
made
no
forfeiture
of
their
lives,
than
he
has
over
any
other, who,
without
any
injuries
or
provocations,
have
lived
upon
fair
terms
with
him. Sect. 180. Thirdly,
The
power a
conqueror
gets
over
those
he
overcomes
in
a
just
war,
is
perfectly despotical:
he
has
an
absolute
power
over
the
lives
of
those, who,
by
putting
themselves
in
a
state
of
war,
have
forfeited
them;
but
he
has
not
thereby
a
right
and
title
to
their
possessions.
This
I
doubt
not,
but
at
first
sight
will
seem
a
strange
doctrine,
it
being
so
quite
contrary
to
the
practice
of
the
world;
there
being
nothing
more
familiar
in
speaking
of
the
dominion
of
countries,
than
to
say
such
an
one
conquered
it;
as
if
conquest,
without
any
more
ado,
conveyed
a
right
of
possession.
But
when
we
consider,
that
the
practice
of
the
strong
and
powerful,
how
universal
soever
it
may
be,
is
seldom
the
rule
of
right, however
it
be
one
part
of
the
subjection
of
the
conquered,
not
to
argue
against
the
conditions
cut
out
to
them
by
the
conquering
sword. Sect. 181.
Though
in
all
war
there
be
usually a
complication
of
force
and
damage,
and
the
aggressor
seldom
fails
to
harm
the
estate,
when
he
uses
force
against
the
persons
of
those
he
makes
war
upon;
yet
it
is
the
use
of
force
only
that
puts
a
man
into
the
state
of
war:
for
whether
by
force
he
begins
the
injury,
or
else
having
quietly,
and
by
fraud,
done
the
injury,
he
refuses
to
make
reparation,
and
by
force
maintains
it, (which
is
the
same
thing,
as
at
first
to
have
done
it
by
force)
it
is
the
unjust
use
of
force
that
makes
the
war:
for
he
that
breaks
open
my house,
and
violently
turns
me
out
of
doors;
or
having
peaceably got in,
by
force
keeps
me
out,
does
in
effect
the
same
thing;
supposing
we
are
in
such
a state,
that
we
have
no
common
judge
on
earth,
whom
I
may
appeal
to,
and
to
whom
we
are
both
obliged
to
submit:
for
of
such
I
am
now
speaking.
It
is
the
unjust
use
of
force
then,
that
puts
a
man
into
the
state
of
war
with
another;
and
thereby
he
that
is
guilty
of
it
makes
a
forfeiture
of
his
life:
for
quitting
reason,
which
is
the
rule
given
between
man
and
man,
and
using
force,
the
way
of
beasts,
he
becomes
liable
to
be
destroyed
by
him
he
uses
force
against,
as
any
savage
ravenous
beast,
that
is
dangerous
to
his
being. Sect. 182.
But
because
the
miscarriages
of
the
father
are
no
faults
of
the
children,
and
they
may
be
rational
and
peaceable,
notwithstanding
the
brutishness
and
injustice
of
the
father;
the
father,
by
his
miscarriages
and
violence,
can
forfeit
but
his
own
life,
but
involves
not
his
children
in
his
guilt
or
destruction.
His
goods,
which
nature,
that
willeth
the
preservation
of
all
mankind
as
much
as
is
possible, hath
made
to
belong
to
the
children
to
keep
them
from
perishing,
do
still
continue
to
belong
to
his
children:
for
supposing
them
not
to
have
joined
in
the
war,
either
thro' infancy, absence,
or
choice,
they
have
done
nothing
to
forfeit
them:
nor
has
the
conqueror
any
right
to
take
them
away,
by
the
bare
title
of
having
subdued
him
that
by
force
attempted
his
destruction;
though
perhaps
he
may
have
some
right
to
them,
to
repair
the
damages
he
has
sustained
by
the
war,
and
the
defence
of
his
own
right;
which
how
far
it
reaches
to
the
possessions
of
the
conquered,
we
shall
see
by
and
by.
So
that
he
that
by
conquest
has a
right
over
a man's
person
to
destroy
him
if
he
pleases, has
not
thereby
a
right
over
his
estate
to
possess
and
enjoy
it:
for
it
is
the
brutal
force
the
aggressor
has used,
that
gives
his
adversary
a
right
to
take
away
his
life,
and
destroy
him
if
he
pleases,
as
a
noxious
creature;
but
it
is
damage
sustained
that
alone
gives
him
title
to
another
man's goods:
for
though
I
may
kill a
thief
that
sets
on
me
in
the
highway,
yet
I
may
not
(which
seems
less)
take
away
his
money,
and
let
him
go:
this
would
be
robbery
on
my side.
His
force,
and
the
state
of
war
he
put
himself
in,
made
him
forfeit
his
life,
but
gave
me
no
title
to
his
goods.
The
right
then
of
conquest
extends
only
to
the
lives
of
those
who
joined
in
the
war,
not
to
their
estates,
but
only
in
order
to
make
reparation
for
the
damages
received,
and
the
charges
of
the
war,
and
that
too
with
reservation
of
the
right
of
the
innocent
wife
and
children. Sect. 183.
Let
the
conqueror
have
as
much
justice
on
his
side,
as
could
be
supposed,
he
has
no
right
to
seize
more
than
the
vanquished
could
forfeit:
his
life
is
at
the
victor's mercy;
and
his
service
and
goods
he
may
appropriate,
to
make
himself
reparation;
but
he
cannot
take
the
goods
of
his
wife
and
children;
they
too
had a title
to
the
goods
he
enjoyed,
and
their
shares
in
the
estate
he
possessed:
for
example, I
in
the
state
of
nature
(and
all
commonwealths
are
in
the
state
of
nature
one
with
another)
have
injured
another
man,
and
refusing
to
give
satisfaction,
it
comes
to
a
state
of
war,
wherein
my
defending
by
force
what
I had
gotten
unjustly,
makes
me
the
aggressor. I
am
conquered: my life,
it
is
true,
as
forfeit,
is
at
mercy,
but
not
my wife's
and
children's.
They
made
not
the
war,
nor
assisted
in
it. I
could
not
forfeit
their
lives;
they
were
not
mine
to
forfeit. My
wife
had a
share
in
my estate;
that
neither
could
I forfeit.
And
my children also, being
born
of
me, had a
right
to
be
maintained
out
of
my
labour
or
substance.
Here
then
is
the
case:
the
conqueror
has a title
to
reparation
for
damages
received,
and
the
children
have
a title
to
their
father's
estate
for
their
subsistence:
for
as
to
the
wife's share,
whether
her
own
labour,
or
compact, gave
her
a title
to
it,
it
is
plain,
her
husband
could
not
forfeit
what
was
her's.
What
must
be
done
in
the
case? I answer;
the
fundamental
law
of
nature
being,
that
all,
as
much
as
may
be,
should
be
preserved,
it
follows,
that
if
there
be
not
enough
fully
to
satisfy
both, viz,
for
the
conqueror's losses,
and
children's maintenance,
he
that
hath,
and
to
spare,
must
remit
something
of
his
full
satisfaction,
and
give
way
to
the
pressing
and
preferable
title
of
those
who
are
in
danger
to
perish
without
it. Sect. 184.
But
supposing
the
charge
and
damages
of
the
war
are
to
be
made
up
to
the
conqueror,
to
the
utmost
farthing;
and
that
the
children
of
the
vanquished, spoiled
of
all
their
father's goods,
are
to
be
left
to
starve
and
perish;
yet
the
satisfying
of
what
shall,
on
this
score,
be
due
to
the
conqueror,
will
scarce
give
him
a title
to
any
country
he
shall
conquer:
for
the
damages
of
war
can
scarce
amount
to
the
value
of
any
considerable
tract
of
land,
in
any
part
of
the
world,
where
all
the
land
is
possessed,
and
none
lies waste.
And
if
I
have
not
taken
away
the
conqueror's land, which, being vanquished,
it
is
impossible
I should;
scarce
any
other
spoil
I
have
done
him
can
amount
to
the
value
of
mine,
supposing
it
equally cultivated,
and
of
an
extent
any
way
coming
near
what
I had
overrun
of
his.
The
destruction
of
a year's
product
or
two
(for
it
seldom
reaches
four
or
five)
is
the
utmost
spoil
that
usually
can
be
done:
for
as
to
money,
and
such
riches
and
treasure
taken away,
these
are
none
of
nature's goods,
they
have
but
a fantastical
imaginary
value:
nature
has
put
no
such
upon
them:
they
are
of
no
more
account
by
her
standard,
than
the
wampompeke
of
the
Americans
to
an
European
prince,
or
the
silver
money
of
Europe
would
have
been
formerly
to
an
American.
And
five
years
product
is
not
worth
the
perpetual
inheritance
of
land,
where
all
is
possessed,
and
none
remains
waste,
to
be
taken
up
by
him
that
is
disseized:
which
will
be
easily granted,
if
one
do
but
take
away
the
imaginary
value
of
money,
the
disproportion being
more
than
between
five
and
five
hundred; though,
at
the
same
time,
half
a year's
product
is
more
worth
than
the
inheritance,
where
there
being
more
land
than
the
inhabitants
possess
and
make
use
of,
any
one
has
liberty
to
make
use
of
the
waste:
but
there
conquerors
take
little
care
to
possess
themselves
of
the
lands
of
the
vanquished,
No
damage
therefore,
that
men
in
the
state
of
nature
(as
all
princes
and
governments
are
in
reference
to
one
another)
suffer
from
one
another,
can
give
a
conqueror
power
to
dispossess
the
posterity
of
the
vanquished,
and
turn
them
out
of
that
inheritance,
which
ought
to
be
the
possession
of
them
and
their
descendants
to
all
generations.
The
conqueror
indeed
will
be
apt
to
think
himself
master:
and
it
is
the
very
condition
of
the
subdued
not
to
be
able
to
dispute
their
right.
But
if
that
be
all,
it
gives
no
other
title
than
what
bare
force
gives
to
the
stronger
over
the
weaker: and,
by
this
reason,
he
that
is
strongest
will
have
a
right
to
whatever
he
pleases
to
seize
on. Sect. 185.
Over
those
then
that
joined
with
him
in
the
war,
and
over
those
of
the
subdued
country
that
opposed
him
not,
and
the
posterity
even
of
those
that
did,
the
conqueror,
even
in
a
just
war, hath,
by
his
conquest,
no
right
of
dominion:
they
are
free
from
any
subjection
to
him,
and
if
their
former
government
be
dissolved,
they
are
at
liberty
to
begin
and
erect
another
to
themselves. Sect. 186.
The
conqueror,
it
is
true, usually,
by
the
force
he
has
over
them,
compels
them,
with
a
sword
at
their
breasts,
to
stoop
to
his
conditions,
and
submit
to
such
a
government
as
he
pleases
to
afford
them;
but
the
enquiry is,
what
right
he
has
to
do
so?
If
it
be
said,
they
submit
by
their
own
consent,
then
this
allows
their
own
consent
to
be
necessary
to
give
the
conqueror
a title
to
rule
over
them.
It
remains
only
to
be
considered,
whether
promises
extorted
by
force,
without
right,
can
be
thought
consent,
and
how
far
they
bind.
To
which
I
shall
say,
they
bind
not
at
all;
because
whatsoever
another
gets
from
me
by
force, I
still
retain
the
right
of,
and
he
is
obliged presently
to
restore.
He
that
forces
my
horse
from
me,
ought
presently
to
restore
him,
and
I
have
still
a
right
to
retake him.
By
the
same
reason,
he
that
forced a
promise
from
me,
ought
presently
to
restore
it, i.e.
quit
me
of
the
obligation
of
it;
or
I
may
resume
it
myself, i.e. chuse
whether
I
will
perform
it:
for
the
law
of
nature
laying
an
obligation
on
me
only
by
the
rules
she
prescribes, cannot
oblige
me
by
the
violation
of
her
rules:
such
is
the
extorting
any
thing
from
me
by
force.
Nor
does
it
at
all
alter
the
case
to
say, I gave my promise,
no
more
than
it
excuses
the
force,
and
passes
the
right,
when
I
put
my
hand
in
my pocket,
and
deliver
my purse
myself
to
a thief,
who
demands
it
with
a
pistol
at
my breast. Sect. 187.
From
all
which
it
follows,
that
the
government
of
a conqueror,
imposed
by
force
on
the
subdued, against
whom
he
had
no
right
of
war,
or
who
joined
not
in
the
war
against him,
where
he
had right, has
no
obligation
upon
them. Sect. 188.
But
let
us
suppose,
that
all
the
men
of
that
community, being
all
members
of
the
same
body
politic,
may
be
taken
to
have
joined
in
that
unjust
war
wherein
they
are
subdued,
and
so
their
lives
are
at
the
mercy
of
the
conqueror. Sect. 189. I
say
this
concerns
not
their
children
who
are
in
their
minority:
for
since
a father hath not,
in
himself, a power
over
the
life
or
liberty
of
his
child,
no
act
of
his
can
possibly
forfeit
it.
So
that
the
children, whatever
may
have
happened
to
the
fathers,
are
freemen,
and
the
absolute
power
of
the
conqueror
reaches
no
farther
than
the
persons
of
the
men
that
were
subdued
by
him,
and
dies
with
them:
and
should
he
govern
them
as
slaves,
subjected
to
his
absolute
arbitrary
power,
he
has
no
such
right
of
dominion
over
their
children.
He
can
have
no
power
over
them
but
by
their
own
consent, whatever
he
may
drive
them
to
say
or
do;
and
he
has
no
lawfull authority, whilst force,
and
not
choice,
compels
them
to
submission. Sect. 190.
Every
man
is
born
with
a
double
right: first, a
right
of
freedom
to
his
person,
which
no
other
man
has a power over,
but
the
free
disposal
of
it
lies
in
himself. Secondly, a right,
before
any
other
man,
to
inherit
with
his
brethren
his
father's goods. Sect. 191.
By
the
first
of
these, a
man
is
naturally
free
from
subjection
to
any
government, tho'
he
be
born
in
a
place
under
its
jurisdiction;
but
if
he
disclaim
the
lawful
government
of
the
country
he
was
born
in,
he
must
also
quit
the
right
that
belonged
to
him
by
the
laws
of
it,
and
the
possessions
there
descending
to
him
from
his
ancestors,
if
it
were
a
government
made
by
their
consent. Sect. 192.
By
the
second,
the
inhabitants
of
any
country,
who
are
descended,
and
derive
a title
to
their
estates
from
those
who
are
subdued,
and
had a
government
forced
upon
them
against
their
free
consents,
retain
a
right
to
the
possession
of
their
ancestors,
though
they
consent
not
freely
to
the
government,
whose
hard
conditions
were
by
force
imposed
on
the
possessors
of
that
country:
for
the
first
conqueror
never
having
had a title
to
the
land
of
that
country,
the
people
who
are
the
descendants
of,
or
claim
under
those
who
were
forced
to
submit
to
the
yoke
of
a
government
by
constraint,
have
always
a
right
to
shake
it
off,
and
free
themselves
from
the
usurpation
or
tyranny
which
the
sword
hath brought
in
upon
them,
till
their
rulers
put
them
under
such
a
frame
of
government
as
they
willingly
and
of
choice
consent
to.
Who
doubts
but
the
Grecian
Christians,
descendants
of
the
ancient
possessors
of
that
country,
may
justly cast
off
the
Turkish
yoke,
which
they
have
so
long
groaned under, whenever
they
have
an
opportunity
to
do
it?
For
no
government
can
have
a
right
to
obedience
from
a
people
who
have
not
freely
consented
to
it;
which
they
can
never
be
supposed
to
do,
till
either
they
are
put
in
a
full
state
of
liberty
to
chuse
their
government
and
governors,
or
at
least
till
they
have
such
standing laws,
to
which
they
have
by
themselves
or
their
representatives
given
their
free
consent,
and
also
till
they
are
allowed
their
due
property,
which
is
so
to
be
proprietors
of
what
they
have,
that
no
body
can
take
away
any
part
of
it
without
their
own
consent,
without
which, men
under
any
government
are
not
in
the
state
of
freemen,
but
are
direct
slaves
under
the
force
of
war. Sect. 193.
But
granting
that
the
conqueror
in
a
just
war
has a
right
to
the
estates,
as
well
as
power
over
the
persons,
of
the
conquered; which,
it
is
plain,
he
hath not:
nothing
of
absolute
power
will
follow
from
hence,
in
the
continuance
of
the
government;
because
the
descendants
of
these
being
all
freemen,
if
he
grants
them
estates
and
possessions
to
inhabit
his
country, (without
which
it
would
be
worth
nothing) whatsoever
he
grants
them,
they
have,
so
far
as
it
is
granted,
property
in.
The
nature
whereof
is,
that
without
a man's
own
consent
it
cannot
be
taken
from
him. Sect. 194.
Their
persons
are
free
by
a
native
right,
and
their
properties,
be
they
more
or
less,
are
their
own,
and
at
their
own
dispose,
and
not
at
his;
or
else
it
is
no
property.
Supposing
the
conqueror
gives
to
one
man
a
thousand
acres,
to
him
and
his
heirs
for
ever;
to
another
he
lets
a
thousand
acres
for
his
life,
under
the
rent
of
50£.
or
500£.
per
arm. has
not
the
one
of
these
a
right
to
his
thousand
acres
for
ever,
and
the
other,
during
his
life, paying
the
said rent?
and
hath
not
the
tenant
for
life
a
property
in
all
that
he
gets
over
and
above
his
rent,
by
his
labour
and
industry
during
the
said term,
supposing
it
be
double
the
rent?
Can
any
one
say,
the
king,
or
conqueror,
after
his
grant,
may
by
his
power
of
conqueror
take
away
all,
or
part
of
the
land
from
the
heirs
of
one,
or
from
the
other
during
his
life,
he
paying
the
rent?
or
can
he
take
away
from
either
the
goods
or
money
they
have
got
upon
the
said land,
at
his
pleasure?
If
he
can,
then
all
free
and
voluntary
contracts
cease,
and
are
void
in
the
world;
there
needs
nothing
to
dissolve
them
at
any
time,
but
power enough:
and
all
the
grants
and
promises
of
men
in
power
are
but
mockery
and
collusion:
for
can
there
be
any
thing
more
ridiculous
than
to
say, I
give
you
and
your's
this
for
ever,
and
that
in
the
surest
and
most
solemn
way
of
conveyance
can
be
devised;
and
yet
it
is
to
be
understood,
that
I
have
right,
if
I please,
to
take
it
away
from
you
again
to
morrow? Sect. 195. I
will
not
dispute
now
whether
princes
are
exempt
from
the
laws
of
their
country;
but
this
I
am
sure,
they
owe
subjection
to
the
laws
of
God
and
nature.
No
body,
no
power,
can
exempt
them
from
the
obligations
of
that
eternal
law.
Those
are
so
great,
and
so
strong,
in
the
case
of
promises,
that
omnipotency
itself
can
be
tied
by
them. Grants, promises,
and
oaths,
are
bonds
that
hold
the
Almighty: whatever
some
flatterers
say
to
princes
of
the
world,
who
all
together,
with
all
their
people
joined
to
them, are,
in
comparison
of
the
great
God,
but
as
a
drop
of
the
bucket,
or
a dust
on
the
balance, inconsiderable, nothing! Sect. 196.
The
short
of
the
case
in
conquest
is
this:
the
conqueror,
if
he
have
a
just
cause, has a despotical
right
over
the
persons
of
all,
that
actually aided,
and
concurred
in
the
war
against him,
and
a
right
to
make
up
his
damage
and
cost
out
of
their
labour
and
estates,
so
he
injure
not
the
right
of
any
other.
Over
the
rest
of
the
people,
if
there
were
any
that
consented
not
to
the
war,
and
over
the
children
of
the
captives
themselves,
or
the
possessions
of
either,
he
has
no
power;
and
so
can
have,
by
virtue
of
conquest,
no
lawful
title
himself
to
dominion
over
them,
or
derive
it
to
his
posterity;
but
is
an
aggressor,
if
he
attempts
upon
their
properties,
and
thereby
puts
himself
in
a
state
of
war
against them,
and
has
no
better
a
right
of
principality, he,
nor
any
of
his
successors,
than
Hingar,
or
Hubba,
the
Danes, had
here
in
England;
or
Spartacus, had
he
conquered
Italy,
would
have
had;
which
is
to
have
their
yoke
cast off,
as
soon
as
God
shall
give
those
under
their
subjection
courage
and
opportunity
to
do
it. Thus,
notwithstanding
whatever title
the
kings
of
Assyria
had
over
Judah,
by
the
sword,
God
assisted Hezekiah
to
throw
off
the
dominion
of
that
conquering
empire.
And
the
lord
was
with
Hezekiah,
and
he
prospered;
wherefore
he
went forth,
and
he
rebelled against
the
king
of
Assyria,
and
served
him
not, 2 Kings xviii. 7.
Whence
it
is
plain,
that
shaking
off
a power,
which
force,
and
not
right, hath
set
over
any
one,
though
it
hath
the
name
of
rebellion,
yet
is
no
offence
before
God,
but
is
that
which
he
allows
and
countenances,
though
even
promises
and
covenants,
when
obtained
by
force,
have
intervened:
for
it
is
very
probable,
to
any
one
that
reads
the
story
of
Ahaz
and
Hezekiah attentively,
that
the
Assyrians subdued Ahaz,
and
deposed
him,
and
made
Hezekiah
king
in
his
father's lifetime;
and
that
Hezekiah
by
agreement
had
done
him
homage,
and
paid
him
tribute
all
this
time.