CHAPTER V. OF PROPERTY.
Sect. 25.
Whether
we
consider
natural
reason,
which
tells
us,
that
men, being
once
born,
have
a
right
to
their
preservation,
and
consequently
to
meat
and
drink,
and
such
other
things
as
nature
affords
for
their
subsistence:
or
revelation,
which
gives
us
an
account
of
those
grants
God
made
of
the
world
to
Adam,
and
to
Noah,
and
his
sons,
it
is
very
clear,
that
God,
as
king
David says, Psal. cxv. 16. has
given
the
earth
to
the
children
of
men;
given
it
to
mankind
in
common.
But
this
being supposed,
it
seems
to
some
a
very
great
difficulty,
how
any
one
should
ever
come
to
have
a
property
in
any
thing: I
will
not
content
myself
to
answer,
that
if
it
be
difficult
to
make
out
property,
upon
a
supposition
that
God
gave
the
world
to
Adam,
and
his
posterity
in
common,
it
is
impossible
that
any
man,
but
one
universal
monarch,
should
have
any
property
upon
a supposition,
that
God
gave
the
world
to
Adam,
and
his
heirs
in
succession,
exclusive
of
all
the
rest
of
his
posterity.
But
I
shall
endeavour
to
shew,
how
men
might
come
to
have
a
property
in
several
parts
of
that
which
God
gave
to
mankind
in
common,
and
that
without
any
express compact
of
all
the
commoners. Sect. 26. God,
who
hath
given
the
world
to
men
in
common, hath
also
given
them
reason
to
make
use
of
it
to
the
best
advantage
of
life,
and
convenience.
The
earth,
and
all
that
is
therein,
is
given
to
men
for
the
support
and
comfort
of
their
being.
And
tho'
all
the
fruits
it
naturally produces,
and
beasts
it
feeds,
belong
to
mankind
in
common,
as
they
are
produced
by
the
spontaneous
hand
of
nature;
and
no
body
has
originally
a
private
dominion,
exclusive
of
the
rest
of
mankind,
in
any
of
them,
as
they
are
thus
in
their
natural
state:
yet
being
given
for
the
use
of
men,
there
must
of
necessity
be
a
means
to
appropriate
them
some
way
or
other,
before
they
can
be
of
any
use,
or
at
all
beneficial
to
any
particular
man.
The
fruit,
or
venison,
which
nourishes
the
wild Indian,
who
knows
no
enclosure,
and
is
still
a
tenant
in
common,
must
be
his,
and
so
his, i.e. a
part
of
him,
that
another
can
no
longer
have
any
right
to
it,
before
it
can
do
him
any
good
for
the
support
of
his
life. Sect. 27.
Though
the
earth,
and
all
inferior creatures,
be
common
to
all
men,
yet
every
man
has a
property
in
his
own
person:
this
no
body
has
any
right
to
but
himself.
The
labour
of
his
body,
and
the
work
of
his
hands,
we
may
say,
are
properly
his. Whatsoever
then
he
removes
out
of
the
state
that
nature
hath provided,
and
left
it
in,
he
hath mixed
his
labour
with,
and
joined
to
it
something
that
is
his
own,
and
thereby
makes
it
his
property.
It
being
by
him
removed
from
the
common
state
nature
hath
placed
it
in,
it
hath
by
this
labour
something
annexed
to
it,
that
excludes
the
common
right
of
other
men:
for
this
labour
being
the
unquestionable
property
of
the
labourer,
no
man
but
he
can
have
a
right
to
what
that
is
once
joined
to,
at
least
where
there
is
enough,
and
as
good, left
in
common
for
others. Sect. 28.
He
that
is
nourished
by
the
acorns
he
picked
up
under
an
oak,
or
the
apples
he
gathered
from
the
trees
in
the
wood, has certainly
appropriated
them
to
himself.
No
body
can
deny
but
the
nourishment
is
his. I
ask
then,
when
did
they
begin
to
be
his?
when
he
digested?
or
when
he
eat?
or
when
he
boiled?
or
when
he
brought
them
home?
or
when
he
picked
them
up?
and
it
is
plain,
if
the
first
gathering
made
them
not
his,
nothing
else
could.
That
labour
put
a
distinction
between
them
and
common:
that
added
something
to
them
more
than
nature,
the
common
mother
of
all, had done;
and
so
they
became
his
private
right.
And
will
any
one
say,
he
had
no
right
to
those
acorns
or
apples,
he
thus
appropriated,
because
he
had
not
the
consent
of
all
mankind
to
make
them
his?
Was
it
a
robbery
thus
to
assume
to
himself
what
belonged
to
all
in
common?
If
such
a
consent
as
that
was
necessary,
man
had starved,
notwithstanding
the
plenty
God
had
given
him.
We
see
in
commons,
which
remain
so
by
compact,
that
it
is
the
taking
any
part
of
what
is
common,
and
removing
it
out
of
the
state
nature
leaves
it
in,
which
begins
the
property;
without
which
the
common
is
of
no
use.
And
the
taking
of
this
or
that
part,
does
not
depend
on
the
express
consent
of
all
the
commoners.
Thus
the
grass
my
horse
has bit;
the
turfs my
servant
has cut;
and
the
ore
I
have
digged
in
any
place,
where
I
have
a
right
to
them
in
common
with
others,
become
my property,
without
the
assignation
or
consent
of
any
body.
The
labour
that
was
mine, removing
them
out
of
that
common
state
they
were
in, hath fixed my
property
in
them. Sect. 29.
By
making
an
explicit
consent
of
every
commoner,
necessary
to
any
one's
appropriating
to
himself
any
part
of
what
is
given
in
common, children
or
servants
could
not
cut
the
meat,
which
their
father
or
master
had provided
for
them
in
common,
without
assigning
to
every
one
his
peculiar
part.
Though
the
water
running
in
the
fountain
be
every
one's,
yet
who
can
doubt,
but
that
in
the
pitcher
is
his
only
who
drew
it
out?
His
labour
hath taken
it
out
of
the
hands
of
nature,
where
it
was
common,
and
belonged
equally
to
all
her
children,
and
hath
thereby
appropriated
it
to
himself. Sect. 30.
Thus
this
law
of
reason
makes
the
deer
that
Indian's
who
hath
killed
it;
it
is
allowed
to
be
his
goods,
who
hath bestowed
his
labour
upon
it,
though
before
it
was
the
common
right
of
every
one.
And
amongst
those
who
are
counted
the
civilized
part
of
mankind,
who
have
made
and
multiplied positive
laws
to
determine
property,
this
original
law
of
nature,
for
the
beginning
of
property,
in
what
was
before
common,
still
takes
place;
and
by
virtue
thereof,
what
fish
any
one
catches
in
the
ocean,
that
great
and
still
remaining
common
of
mankind;
or
what
ambergrise
any
one
takes
up
here,
is
by
the
labour
that
removes
it
out
of
that
common
state
nature
left
it
in,
made
his
property,
who
takes
that
pains
about
it.
And
even
amongst
us,
the
hare
that
any
one
is
hunting,
is
thought
his
who
pursues
her
during
the
chase:
for
being a
beast
that
is
still
looked
upon
as
common,
and
no
man's
private
possession;
whoever
has
employed
so
much
labour
about
any
of
that
kind,
as
to
find
and
pursue
her, has
thereby
removed
her
from
the
state
of
nature,
wherein
she
was
common,
and
hath begun a property. Sect. 31.
It
will
perhaps
be
objected
to
this,
that
if
gathering
the
acorns,
or
other
fruits
of
the
earth, &c.
makes
a
right
to
them,
then
any
one
may
ingross
as
much
as
he
will.
To
which
I answer,
Not
so.
The
same
law
of
nature,
that
does
by
this
means
give
us
property,
does
also
bound
that
property
too.
God
has
given
us
all
things
richly, 1 Tim. vi. 12.
is
the
voice
of
reason
confirmed
by
inspiration.
But
how
far
has
he
given
it
us?
To
enjoy.
As
much
as
any
one
can
make
use
of
to
any
advantage
of
life
before
it
spoils,
so
much
he
may
by
his
Tabour
fix
a
property
in: whatever
is
beyond
this,
is
more
than
his
share,
and
belongs
to
others.
Nothing
was
made
by
God
for
man
to
spoil
or
destroy.
And
thus,
considering
the
plenty
of
natural
provisions
there
was
a
long
time
in
the
world,
and
the
few
spenders;
and
to
how
small a
part
of
that
provision
the
industry
of
one
man
could
extend
itself,
and
ingross
it
to
the
prejudice
of
others; especially
keeping
within
the
bounds,
set
by
reason,
of
what
might
serve
for
his
use;
there
could
be
then
little
room
for
quarrels
or
contentions
about
property
so
established. Sect. 32.
But
the
chief
matter
of
property
being
now
not
the
fruits
of
the
earth,
and
the
beasts
that
subsist
on
it,
but
the
earth
itself;
as
that
which
takes
in
and
carries
with
it
all
the
rest; I
think
it
is
plain,
that
property
in
that
too
is
acquired
as
the
former.
As
much
land
as
a
man
tills, plants, improves, cultivates,
and
can
use
the
product
of,
so
much
is
his
property.
He
by
his
labour
does,
as
it
were, inclose
it
from
the
common.
Nor
will
it
invalidate
his
right,
to
say
every
body
else
has
an
equal title
to
it;
and
therefore
he
cannot appropriate,
he
cannot inclose,
without
the
consent
of
all
his
fellow-commoners,
all
mankind. God,
when
he
gave
the
world
in
common
to
all
mankind,
commanded
man
also
to
labour,
and
the
penury
of
his
condition required
it
of
him.
God
and
his
reason
commanded
him
to
subdue
the
earth, i.e.
improve
it
for
the
benefit
of
life,
and
therein
lay
out
something
upon
it
that
was
his
own,
his
labour.
He
that
in
obedience
to
this
command
of
God, subdued, tilled
and
sowed
any
part
of
it,
thereby
annexed
to
it
something
that
was
his
property,
which
another
had
no
title to,
nor
could
without
injury
take
from
him. Sect. 33.
Nor
was
this
appropriation
of
any
parcel
of
land,
by
improving
it,
any
prejudice
to
any
other
man,
since
there
was
still
enough,
and
as
good
left;
and
more
than
the
yet
unprovided
could
use.
So
that,
in
effect,
there
was
never
the
less
left
for
others
because
of
his
enclosure
for
himself:
for
he
that
leaves
as
much
as
another
can
make
use
of,
does
as
good
as
take
nothing
at
all.
No
body
could
think
himself
injured
by
the
drinking
of
another
man,
though
he
took
a
good
draught,
who
had a
whole
river
of
the
same
water
left
him
to
quench
his
thirst:
and
the
case
of
land
and
water,
where
there
is
enough
of
both,
is
perfectly
the
same. Sect. 34.
God
gave
the
world
to
men
in
common;
but
since
he
gave
it
them
for
their
benefit,
and
the
greatest conveniencies
of
life
they
were
capable
to
draw
from
it,
it
cannot
be
supposed
he
meant
it
should
always
remain
common
and
uncultivated.
He
gave
it
to
the
use
of
the
industrious
and
rational, (and
labour
was
to
be
his
title
to
it;)
not
to
the
fancy
or
covetousness
of
the
quarrelsome
and
contentious.
He
that
had
as
good
left
for
his
improvement,
as
was
already
taken up,
needed
not
complain,
ought
not
to
meddle
with
what
was
already
improved
by
another's labour:
if
he
did,
it
is
plain
he
desired
the
benefit
of
another's pains,
which
he
had
no
right
to,
and
not
the
ground
which
God
had
given
him
in
common
with
others
to
labour
on,
and
whereof
there
was
as
good
left,
as
that
already
possessed,
and
more
than
he
knew
what
to
do
with,
or
his
industry
could
reach to. Sect. 35.
It
is
true,
in
land
that
is
common
in
England,
or
any
other
country,
where
there
is
plenty
of
people
under
government,
who
have
money
and
commerce,
no
one
can
inclose
or
appropriate
any
part,
without
the
consent
of
all
his
fellow-commoners;
because
this
is
left
common
by
compact, i.e.
by
the
law
of
the
land,
which
is
not
to
be
violated.
And
though
it
be
common,
in
respect
of
some
men,
it
is
not
so
to
all
mankind;
but
is
the
joint
property
of
this
country,
or
this
parish. Besides,
the
remainder,
after
such
enclosure,
would
not
be
as
good
to
the
rest
of
the
commoners,
as
the
whole
was
when
they
could
all
make
use
of
the
whole; whereas
in
the
beginning
and
first
peopling
of
the
great
common
of
the
world,
it
was
quite
otherwise.
The
law
man
was
under,
was
rather
for
appropriating.
God
commanded,
and
his
wants
forced
him
to
labour.
That
was
his
property
which
could
not
be
taken
from
him
where-ever
he
had fixed it.
And
hence
subduing
or
cultivating
the
earth,
and
having
dominion,
we
see
are
joined
together.
The
one
gave title
to
the
other.
So
that
God,
by
commanding
to
subdue, gave
authority
so
far
to
appropriate:
and
the
condition
of
human
life,
which
requires
labour
and
materials
to
work
on, necessarily
introduces
private
possessions. Sect. 36.
The
measure
of
property
nature
has
well
set
by
the
extent
of
men's
labour
and
the
conveniencies
of
life:
no
man's
labour
could
subdue,
or
appropriate
all;
nor
could
his
enjoyment
consume
more
than
a small part;
so
that
it
was
impossible
for
any
man,
this
way,
to
intrench
upon
the
right
of
another,
or
acquire
to
himself
a property,
to
the
prejudice
of
his
neighbour,
who
would
still
have
room
for
as
good,
and
as
large
a
possession
(after
the
other
had taken
out
his)
as
before
it
was
appropriated.
This
measure
did
confine
every
man's
possession
to
a
very
moderate proportion,
and
such
as
he
might
appropriate
to
himself,
without
injury
to
any
body,
in
the
first
ages
of
the
world,
when
men
were
more
in
danger
to
be
lost,
by
wandering
from
their
company,
in
the
then
vast
wilderness
of
the
earth,
than
to
be
straitened
for
want
of
room
to
plant
in.
And
the
same
measure
may
be
allowed
still
without
prejudice
to
any
body,
as
full
as
the
world
seems:
for
supposing
a man,
or
family,
in
the
state
they
were
at
first
peopling
of
the
world
by
the
children
of
Adam,
or
Noah;
let
him
plant
in
some
inland,
vacant
places
of
America,
we
shall
find
that
the
possessions
he
could
make
himself,
upon
the
measures
we
have
given,
would
not
be
very
large, nor,
even
to
this
day, prejudice
the
rest
of
mankind,
or
give
them
reason
to
complain,
or
think
themselves
injured
by
this
man's incroachment,
though
the
race
of
men
have
now
spread
themselves
to
all
the
corners
of
the
world,
and
do
infinitely
exceed
the
small
number
was
at
the
beginning. Nay,
the
extent
of
ground
is
of
so
little
value,
without
labour,
that
I
have
heard
it
affirmed,
that
in
Spain
itself
a
man
may
be
permitted
to
plough,
sow
and
reap,
without
being disturbed,
upon
land
he
has
no
other
title to,
but
only
his
making
use
of
it. But,
on
the
contrary,
the
inhabitants
think
themselves
beholden
to
him, who,
by
his
industry
on
neglected,
and
consequently
waste
land, has increased
the
stock
of
corn,
which
they
wanted.
But
be
this
as
it
will,
which
I
lay
no
stress
on;
this
I
dare
boldly
affirm,
that
the
same
rule
of
propriety, (viz.)
that
every
man
should
have
as
much
as
he
could
make
use
of,
would
hold
still
in
the
world,
without
straitening
any
body;
since
there
is
land
enough
in
the
world
to
suffice
double
the
inhabitants, had
not
the
invention
of
money,
and
the
tacit
agreement
of
men
to
put
a
value
on
it,
introduced
(by consent) larger possessions,
and
a
right
to
them; which,
how
it
has done, I
shall
by
and
by
shew
more
at
large. Sect. 37.
This
is
certain,
that
in
the
beginning,
before
the
desire
of
having
more
than
man
needed
had
altered
the
intrinsic
value
of
things,
which
depends
only
on
their
usefulness
to
the
life
of
man;
or
had agreed,
that
a
little
piece
of
yellow
metal,
which
would
keep
without
wasting
or
decay,
should
be
worth
a
great
piece
of
flesh,
or
a
whole
heap
of
corn;
though
men had a
right
to
appropriate,
by
their
labour,
each
one
of
himself,
as
much
of
the
things
of
nature,
as
he
could
use:
yet
this
could
not
be
much,
nor
to
the
prejudice
of
others,
where
the
same
plenty
was
still
left
to
those
who
would
use
the
same
industry.
To
which
let
me
add,
that
he
who
appropriates
land
to
himself
by
his
labour,
does
not
lessen,
but
increase
the
common
stock
of
mankind:
for
the
provisions serving
to
the
support
of
human
life, produced
by
one
acre
of
inclosed
and
cultivated
land,
are
(to
speak
much
within
compass)
ten
times
more
than
those
which
are
yielded
by
an
acre
of
land
of
an
equal richness lying
waste
in
common.
And
therefore
he
that
incloses land,
and
has a
greater
plenty
of
the
conveniencies
of
life
from
ten
acres,
than
he
could
have
from
an
hundred
left
to
nature,
may
truly
be
said
to
give
ninety
acres
to
mankind:
for
his
labour
now
supplies
him
with
provisions
out
of
ten
acres,
which
were
but
the
product
of
an
hundred
lying
in
common. I
have
here
rated
the
improved
land
very
low,
in
making
its
product
but
as
ten
to
one,
when
it
is
much
nearer
an
hundred
to
one:
for
I ask,
whether
in
the
wild
woods
and
uncultivated
waste
of
America, left
to
nature,
without
any
improvement, tillage
or
husbandry, a
thousand
acres
yield
the
needy
and
wretched
inhabitants
as
many
conveniencies
of
life,
as
ten
acres
of
equally
fertile
land
do
in
Devonshire,
where
they
are
well
cultivated?
Before
the
appropriation
of
land,
he
who
gathered
as
much
of
the
wild fruit, killed, caught,
or
tamed,
as
many
of
the
beasts,
as
he
could;
he
that
so
imployed
his
pains
about
any
of
the
spontaneous
products
of
nature,
as
any
way
to
alter
them
from
the
state
which
nature
put
them
in,
by
placing
any
of
his
labour
on
them,
did
thereby
acquire
a
propriety
in
them:
but
if
they
perished,
in
his
possession,
without
their
due
use;
if
the
fruits
rotted,
or
the
venison
putrified,
before
he
could
spend
it,
he
offended
against
the
common
law
of
nature,
and
was
liable
to
be
punished;
he
invaded
his
neighbour's share,
for
he
had
no
right,
farther
than
his
use
called
for
any
of
them,
and
they
might
serve
to
afford
him
conveniencies
of
life. Sect. 38.
The
same
measures
governed
the
possession
of
land
too: whatsoever
he
tilled
and
reaped, laid
up
and
made
use
of,
before
it
spoiled,
that
was
his
peculiar
right; whatsoever
he
enclosed,
and
could
feed,
and
make
use
of,
the
cattle
and
product
was
also
his.
But
if
either
the
grass
of
his
enclosure
rotted
on
the
ground,
or
the
fruit
of
his
planting
perished
without
gathering,
and
laying
up,
this
part
of
the
earth,
notwithstanding
his
enclosure,
was
still
to
be
looked
on
as
waste,
and
might
be
the
possession
of
any
other. Thus,
at
the
beginning,
Cain
might
take
as
much
ground
as
he
could
till,
and
make
it
his
own
land,
and
yet
leave
enough
to
Abel's
sheep
to
feed on; a
few
acres
would
serve
for
both
their
possessions.
But
as
families
increased,
and
industry
inlarged
their
stocks,
their
possessions
inlarged
with
the
need
of
them;
but
yet
it
was
commonly
without
any
fixed
property
in
the
ground
they
made
use
of,
till
they
incorporated, settled
themselves
together,
and
built cities;
and
then,
by
consent,
they
came
in
time,
to
set
out
the
bounds
of
their
distinct
territories,
and
agree
on
limits
between
them
and
their
neighbours;
and
by
laws
within
themselves, settled
the
properties
of
those
of
the
same
society:
for
we
see,
that
in
that
part
of
the
world
which
was
first
inhabited,
and
therefore
like
to
be
best
peopled,
even
as
low
down
as
Abraham's time,
they
wandered
with
their
flocks,
and
their
herds,
which
was
their
substance,
freely
up
and
down;
and
this
Abraham
did,
in
a
country
where
he
was
a stranger.
Whence
it
is
plain,
that
at
least
a
great
part
of
the
land
lay
in
common;
that
the
inhabitants
valued
it
not,
nor
claimed
property
in
any
more
than
they
made
use
of.
But
when
there
was
not
room
enough
in
the
same
place,
for
their
herds
to
feed together,
they
by
consent,
as
Abraham
and
Lot
did, Gen. xiii. 5. separated
and
inlarged
their
pasture,
where
it
best
liked
them.
And
for
the
same
reason
Esau went
from
his
father,
and
his
brother,
and
planted
in
mount
Seir, Gen. xxxvi. 6. Sect. 39.
And
thus,
without
supposing
any
private
dominion,
and
property
in
Adam,
over
all
the
world,
exclusive
of
all
other
men,
which
can
no
way
be
proved,
nor
any
one's
property
be
made
out
from
it;
but
supposing
the
world
given,
as
it
was,
to
the
children
of
men
in
common,
we
see
how
labour
could
make
men
distinct
titles
to
several
parcels
of
it,
for
their
private
uses;
wherein
there
could
be
no
doubt
of
right,
no
room
for
quarrel. Sect. 40.
Nor
is
it
so
strange,
as
perhaps
before
consideration
it
may
appear,
that
the
property
of
labour
should
be
able
to
over-balance
the
community
of
land:
for
it
is
labour
indeed
that
puts
the
difference
of
value
on
every
thing;
and
let
any
one
consider
what
the
difference
is
between
an
acre
of
land
planted
with
tobacco
or
sugar, sown
with
wheat
or
barley,
and
an
acre
of
the
same
land
lying
in
common,
without
any
husbandry
upon
it,
and
he
will
find,
that
the
improvement
of
labour
makes
the
far
greater
part
of
the
value. I
think
it
will
be
but
a
very
modest
computation
to
say,
that
of
the
products
of
the
earth
useful
to
the
life
of
man
nine
tenths
are
the
effects
of
labour: nay,
if
we
will
rightly
estimate
things
as
they
come
to
our
use,
and
cast
up
the
several
expences
about
them,
what
in
them
is
purely
owing
to
nature,
and
what
to
labour,
we
shall
find,
that
in
most
of
them
ninety-nine
hundredths
are
wholly
to
be
put
on
the
account
of
labour. Sect. 41.
There
cannot
be
a clearer
demonstration
of
any
thing,
than
several
nations
of
the
Americans
are
of
this,
who
are
rich
in
land,
and
poor
in
all
the
comforts
of
life;
whom
nature
having
furnished
as
liberally
as
any
other
people,
with
the
materials
of
plenty, i.e. a fruitful soil,
apt
to
produce
in
abundance,
what
might
serve
for
food, raiment,
and
delight;
yet
for
want
of
improving
it
by
labour,
have
not
one
hundredth
part
of
the
conveniencies
we
enjoy:
and
a
king
of
a
large
and
fruitful
territory
there, feeds, lodges,
and
is
clad
worse
than
a day-labourer
in
England. Sect. 42.
To
make
this
a
little
clearer,
let
us
but
trace
some
of
the
ordinary
provisions
of
life,
through
their
several
progresses,
before
they
come
to
our
use,
and
see
how
much
they
receive
of
their
value
from
human
industry. Bread, wine
and
cloth,
are
things
of
daily
use,
and
great
plenty;
yet
notwithstanding, acorns,
water
and
leaves,
or
skins,
must
be
our
bread,
drink
and
cloathing,
did
not
labour
furnish
us
with
these
more
useful commodities:
for
whatever bread
is
more
worth
than
acorns, wine
than
water,
and
cloth
or
silk,
than
leaves, skins
or
moss,
that
is
wholly
owing
to
labour
and
industry;
the
one
of
these
being
the
food
and
raiment
which
unassisted
nature
furnishes
us
with;
the
other, provisions
which
our
industry
and
pains
prepare
for
us,
which
how
much
they
exceed
the
other
in
value,
when
any
one
hath computed,
he
will
then
see
how
much
labour
makes
the
far
greatest
part
of
the
value
of
things
we
enjoy
in
this
world:
and
the
ground
which
produces
the
materials,
is
scarce
to
be
reckoned
in,
as
any,
or
at
most,
but
a
very
small
part
of
it;
so
little,
that
even
amongst
us,
land
that
is
left
wholly
to
nature,
that
hath
no
improvement
of
pasturage, tillage,
or
planting,
is
called,
as
indeed
it
is, waste;
and
we
shall
find
the
benefit
of
it
amount
to
little
more
than
nothing.
This
shews
how
much
numbers
of
men
are
to
be
preferred
to
largeness
of
dominions;
and
that
the
increase
of
lands,
and
the
right
employing
of
them,
is
the
great
art
of
government:
and
that
prince,
who
shall
be
so
wise
and
godlike,
as
by
established
laws
of
liberty
to
secure
protection
and
encouragement
to
the
honest
industry
of
mankind, against
the
oppression
of
power
and
narrowness
of
party,
will
quickly
be
too
hard
for
his
neighbours:
but
this
by
the
by.
To
return
to
the
argument
in
hand. Sect. 43.
An
acre
of
land,
that
bears
here
twenty
bushels
of
wheat,
and
another
in
America, which,
with
the
same
husbandry,
would
do
the
like, are,
without
doubt,
of
the
same
natural
intrinsic
value:
but
yet
the
benefit
mankind
receives
from
the
one
in
a year,
is
worth
5l.
and
from
the
other
possibly
not
worth
a penny,
if
all
the
profit
an
Indian received
from
it
were
to
be
valued,
and
sold
here;
at
least, I
may
truly
say,
not
one
thousandth.
It
is
labour
then
which
puts
the
greatest
part
of
value
upon
land,
without
which
it
would
scarcely
be
worth
any
thing:
it
is
to
that
we
owe
the
greatest
part
of
all
its
useful products;
for
all
that
the
straw, bran, bread,
of
that
acre
of
wheat,
is
more
worth
than
the
product
of
an
acre
of
as
good
land,
which
lies waste,
is
all
the
effect
of
labour:
for
it
is
not
barely
the
plough-man's pains,
the
reaper's
and
thresher's toil,
and
the
baker's sweat,
is
to
be
counted
into
the
bread
we
eat;
the
labour
of
those
who
broke
the
oxen,
who
digged
and
wrought
the
iron
and
stones,
who
felled
and
framed
the
timber
employed
about
the
plough, mill, oven,
or
any
other
utensils,
which
are
a
vast
number,
requisite
to
this
corn,
from
its
being feed
to
be
sown
to
its
being
made
bread,
must
all
be
charged
on
the
account
of
labour,
and
received
as
an
effect
of
that:
nature
and
the
earth
furnished
only
the
almost
worthless materials,
as
in
themselves.
It
would
be
a
strange
catalogue
of
things,
that
industry
provided
and
made
use
of,
about
every
loaf
of
bread,
before
it
came
to
our
use,
if
we
could
trace
them; iron, wood, leather, bark, timber, stone, bricks, coals, lime, cloth, dying drugs, pitch, tar, masts, ropes,
and
all
the
materials
made
use
of
in
the
ship,
that
brought
any
of
the
commodities
made
use
of
by
any
of
the
workmen,
to
any
part
of
the
work;
all
which
it
would
be
almost
impossible,
at
least
too
long,
to
reckon
up. Sect. 44.
From
all
which
it
is
evident,
that
though
the
things
of
nature
are
given
in
common,
yet
man,
by
being
master
of
himself,
and
proprietor
of
his
own
person,
and
the
actions
or
labour
of
it, had
still
in
himself
the
great
foundation
of
property;
and
that,
which
made
up
the
great
part
of
what
he
applied
to
the
support
or
comfort
of
his
being,
when
invention
and
arts
had
improved
the
conveniencies
of
life,
was
perfectly
his
own,
and
did
not
belong
in
common
to
others. Sect. 45.
Thus
labour,
in
the
beginning, gave a
right
of
property, wherever
any
one
was
pleased
to
employ
it
upon
what
was
common,
which
remained
a
long
while
the
far
greater
part,
and
is
yet
more
than
mankind
makes
use
of. Men,
at
first,
for
the
most
part,
contented
themselves
with
what
unassisted
nature
offered
to
their
necessities:
and
though
afterwards,
in
some
parts
of
the
world, (where
the
increase
of
people
and
stock,
with
the
use
of
money, had
made
land
scarce,
and
so
of
some
value)
the
several
communities
settled
the
bounds
of
their
distinct
territories,
and
by
laws
within
themselves
regulated
the
properties
of
the
private
men
of
their
society,
and
so,
by
compact
and
agreement, settled
the
property
which
labour
and
industry
began;
and
the
leagues
that
have
been
made
between
several
states
and
kingdoms,
either
expresly
or
tacitly
disowning
all
claim
and
right
to
the
land
in
the
others
possession, have,
by
common
consent,
given
up
their
pretences
to
their
natural
common
right,
which
originally
they
had
to
those
countries,
and
so
have,
by
positive agreement, settled a
property
amongst
themselves,
in
distinct
parts
and
parcels
of
the
earth;
yet
there
are
still
great
tracts
of
ground
to
be
found,
which
(the
inhabitants
thereof
not
having
joined
with
the
rest
of
mankind,
in
the
consent
of
the
use
of
their
common
money)
lie
waste,
and
are
more
than
the
people
who
dwell
on
it
do,
or
can
make
use
of,
and
so
still
lie
in
common; tho'
this
can
scarce
happen
amongst
that
part
of
mankind
that
have
consented
to
the
use
of
money. Sect. 46.
The
greatest
part
of
things
really useful
to
the
life
of
man,
and
such
as
the
necessity
of
subsisting
made
the
first
commoners
of
the
world
look
after,
as
it
doth
the
Americans now,
are
generally
things
of
short
duration;
such
as,
if
they
are
not
consumed
by
use,
will
decay
and
perish
of
themselves: gold,
silver
and
diamonds,
are
things
that
fancy
or
agreement
hath
put
the
value
on,
more
than
real
use,
and
the
necessary
support
of
life.
Now
of
those
good
things
which
nature
hath provided
in
common,
every
one
had a
right
(as hath been said)
to
as
much
as
he
could
use,
and
property
in
all
that
he
could
effect
with
his
labour;
all
that
his
industry
could
extend
to,
to
alter
from
the
state
nature
had
put
it
in,
was
his.
He
that
gathered
a
hundred
bushels
of
acorns
or
apples, had
thereby
a
property
in
them,
they
were
his
goods
as
soon
as
gathered.
He
was
only
to
look,
that
he
used
them
before
they
spoiled,
else
he
took
more
than
his
share,
and
robbed
others.
And
indeed
it
was
a
foolish
thing,
as
well
as
dishonest,
to
hoard
up
more
than
he
could
make
use
of.
If
he
gave
away
a
part
to
any
body
else,
so
that
it
perished
not
uselesly
in
his
possession,
these
he
also
made
use
of.
And
if
he
also
bartered
away
plums,
that
would
have
rotted
in
a week,
for
nuts
that
would
last
good
for
his
eating
a
whole
year,
he
did
no
injury;
he
wasted
not
the
common
stock;
destroyed
no
part
of
the
portion
of
goods
that
belonged
to
others,
so
long
as
nothing
perished
uselesly
in
his
hands. Again,
if
he
would
give
his
nuts
for
a
piece
of
metal, pleased
with
its
colour;
or
exchange
his
sheep
for
shells,
or
wool
for
a sparkling
pebble
or
a diamond,
and
keep
those
by
him
all
his
life
he
invaded
not
the
right
of
others,
he
might
heap
up
as
much
of
these
durable
things
as
he
pleased;
the
exceeding
of
the
bounds
of
his
just
property
not
lying
in
the
largeness
of
his
possession,
but
the
perishing
of
any
thing
uselesly
in
it. Sect. 47.
And
thus
came
in
the
use
of
money,
some
lasting
thing
that
men
might
keep
without
spoiling,
and
that
by
mutual
consent
men
would
take
in
exchange
for
the
truly
useful,
but
perishable
supports
of
life. Sect. 48.
And
as
different
degrees
of
industry
were
apt
to
give
men
possessions
in
different
proportions,
so
this
invention
of
money
gave
them
the
opportunity
to
continue
and
enlarge
them:
for
supposing
an
island,
separate
from
all
possible
commerce
with
the
rest
of
the
world,
wherein
there
were
but
an
hundred
families,
but
there
were
sheep,
horses
and
cows,
with
other
useful animals, wholsome fruits,
and
land
enough
for
corn
for
a
hundred
thousand
times
as
many,
but
nothing
in
the
island,
either
because
of
its
commonness,
or
perishableness, fit
to
supply
the
place
of
money;
what
reason
could
any
one
have
there
to
enlarge
his
possessions
beyond
the
use
of
his
family,
and
a plentiful supply
to
its
consumption,
either
in
what
their
own
industry
produced,
or
they
could
barter
for
like
perishable, useful commodities,
with
others?
Where
there
is
not
some
thing,
both
lasting
and
scarce,
and
so
valuable
to
be
hoarded
up,
there
men
will
not
be
apt
to
enlarge
their
possessions
of
land,
were
it
never
so
rich,
never
so
free
for
them
to
take:
for
I ask,
what
would
a
man
value
ten
thousand,
or
an
hundred
thousand
acres
of
excellent
land,
ready
cultivated,
and
well
stocked
too
with
cattle,
in
the
middle
of
the
inland
parts
of
America,
where
he
had
no
hopes
of
commerce
with
other
parts
of
the
world,
to
draw
money
to
him
by
the
sale
of
the
product?
It
would
not
be
worth
the
enclosing,
and
we
should
see
him
give
up
again
to
the
wild
common
of
nature, whatever
was
more
than
would
supply
the
conveniencies
of
life
to
be
had
there
for
him
and
his
family. Sect. 49.
Thus
in
the
beginning
all
the
world
was
America,
and
more
so
than
that
is
now;
for
no
such
thing
as
money
was
any
where
known. Find
out
something
that
hath
the
use
and
value
of
money
amongst
his
neighbours,
you
shall
see
the
same
man
will
begin
presently
to
enlarge
his
possessions. Sect. 50.
But
since
gold
and
silver, being
little
useful
to
the
life
of
man
in
proportion
to
food, raiment,
and
carriage, has
its
value
only
from
the
consent
of
men,
whereof
labour
yet
makes,
in
great
part,
the
measure,
it
is
plain,
that
men
have
agreed
to
a disproportionate
and
unequal
possession
of
the
earth,
they
having,
by
a
tacit
and
voluntary
consent, found out, a
way
how
a
man
may
fairly
possess
more
land
than
he
himself
can
use
the
product
of,
by
receiving
in
exchange
for
the
overplus
gold
and
silver,
which
may
be
hoarded
up
without
injury
to
any
one;
these
metals
not
spoiling
or
decaying
in
the
hands
of
the
possessor.
This
partage
of
things
in
an
inequality
of
private
possessions, men
have
made
practicable
out
of
the
bounds
of
society,
and
without
compact,
only
by
putting
a
value
on
gold
and
silver,
and
tacitly
agreeing
in
the
use
of
money:
for
in
governments,
the
laws
regulate
the
right
of
property,
and
the
possession
of
land
is
determined
by
positive constitutions. Sect. 51.
And
thus, I think,
it
is
very
easy
to
conceive,
without
any
difficulty,
how
labour
could
at
first
begin
a title
of
property
in
the
common
things
of
nature,
and
how
the
spending
it
upon
our
uses
bounded it.
So
that
there
could
then
be
no
reason
of
quarrelling
about
title,
nor
any
doubt
about
the
largeness
of
possession
it
gave.
Right
and
conveniency went together;
for
as
a
man
had a
right
to
all
he
could
employ
his
labour
upon,
so
he
had
no
temptation
to
labour
for
more
than
he
could
make
use
of.
This
left
no
room
for
controversy
about
the
title,
nor
for
encroachment
on
the
right
of
others;
what
portion
a
man
carved
to
himself,
was
easily seen;
and
it
was
useless,
as
well
as
dishonest,
to
carve
himself
too
much,
or
take
more
than
he
needed.